Editors Choice

The Golden Rule for Lawyers. Lying.

Lying law­yers are most likely to deceive clients in trying to get business, keeping business and making money from business.

COMMENTARIES

 LYING TO CLIENTS FOR ECONOMIC GAIN OR PATERNALISTIC JUDGMENT: A PROPOSAL FOR A GOLDEN RULE OF CANDOR

CARRIE MENKEL-MEADOW*

Lisa Lerman’s article, Lying to Clients, 1 raises very important questions and answers them in part. She asks if the provisions of the ethical codes prohibit lawyers from ever lying to their clients,2 why do lawyers lie (she tells us with exploratory empirical data that they clearly do3) , and in what circumstances can they justify such behavior.

Her reports from twenty interviewed lawyers 4 tell us that law­yers are most likely to deceive clients in trying to get business (puf­fing or exaggerating their expertise and experience),  keeping business (failing to disclose their mistakes, “falsely” impressing cli­ents, failing to disclose accurately the progress of work, and engag­ing in strategic deception in casework), and making money from business (billing practices).

She reviews the justifications that might be offered for such deceptive practices, adopting a philosophical, if not economic, cost and benefit analysis, by analyzing the harms and benefits “caused” by such deception.

*Professor of Law, University of California, Los Angeles; Acting Co-Director, UCLA Center for the Study of Women. A.B. 1971, Barnard College, J.D. i974, University of Pennsylvania. Thanks to Robert Meadow and David Dolinko for their critical comments and suggestions.

I Lerman, Lying to Clients, 138 U. PA. L. REV. 659 (1990).

2 See MODEL RULES OF PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT Rules 8.4, 1.4, 2.1 (1983); MODEL CODE OF PROFESSIONAL RESPONSIBILITY DR 1-102 (A}(4) (1981).

3 See Lerman, supra note 1, at 705-44.

4 A group that hardly can be called a sample of anything other than  some lawyers who agreed to talk about lawyer deception. The numbers are small; the lawyers may easily represent a biased group-those willing to talk about some forms of deception. Professor Lerman calls this “casual empiricism.” As a social scientist, I prefer to call this an exploratory study.

She engages us briefly in the important professional ethics issue of whether specific regulation or hortatory standards are best suited to encouraging good behavior on the part of lawyers.

Professor Lerman concludes her discussion of these issues with some suggested new ethical rules that would require greater candor than lawyers seem now to be providing, particularly with reference to their billing practices,5 their self-presentation for purposes of obtaining clients,6 and their reports to clients about the progress of work for which they have contracted.7

She also suggests that rules about reporting ethical violations should be modified. Rather than requiring lawyers to “snitch” on each other to disciplinary commit­tees,8 they should instead confront each other, with the lawyer per­ceiving the ethical violation suggesting alternative courses of action.9

I think these suggestions are sound and I would support them, if asked  to, by the appropriate  disciplinary  legislative  body  in  my state. 10

5 See Lerman, supra note l, at 749-52.

6    See id. at 753-54.

7   See id. at 755-56.

8 See MODEL RULES OF PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT 8.3; MODEL CODE OF PROFESSIONAL RESPONSIBILITY DR l-103(A).

9 See Lerman, supra note l, at 756-57. Professor Lerman  suggests  that  if one lawyer is junior to another the duty to confront can be transferred to  another,  more senior member of the firm. Though it is beyond the scope  of  this  Comment,  the question of responsibility for the conduct  of  lawyers  within  the supervisory  chain  is an important one, demanding further consideration. In drafting the Model Rules, the Kutak Commission provided junior lawyers with the “defense” that they relied on “reasonable resolution of an arguable question of professional duty,” MODEL RULE 5.2(b). The junior lawyer thus is offered the defense in any subsequent disciplinary proceeding that she “was simply  following  orders”  (and  ethical  rules!).  I  disagree with this  hierarchical  and  allegedly  “more  realistic”  approach  to  legal decisionmaking because it inscribes a lack of professional responsibility in servility to law firm stratification. As a teacher of professional responsibility, I find this approach particularly troubling because I see the most junior lawyers, who have been  educated after Watergate and subject to new  ABA  standards  requiring  instruction  in professional responsibility, as the  most  equipped  to  make  sound  ethical  judgments. See ABA STANDARDS FOR APPROVAL OF LAw SCHOOLS Standard 302(a)(iv)(l988). The junior lawyers not only know  the rules  much  better  than  their seniors,  but  they may be better able to  detect  ethical  conflicts  because  their  attachments  to  important clients tend to be weaker.

10 Although the ABA  “promulgates”  ethical  rules,  these  do  not  have  the  force of law unless the appropriate state  body  enacts  them  into law. In  some states  this is the Supreme Court, in others the legislature and in still others the State Bar itself,  or some disciplinary committee is delegated such authority. In California, all of  these bodies play some role in ethical regulation. See CAL. RULES OF PROF. CONDUCT Rule 1-100 (West 1989) (adopted by the State Bar and  approved  by  the  State  Supreme Court pursuant to statutory authority); CAL. Bus. & PROF. CODE §§ 6067-68,  6100-  18, 6125-33, 6150-55 (West  1974  &  Supp.  1989)  (statutes  regulating,  respectively, the attorney’s oath and duty, authority of Supreme Court  to  discipline  attorney, unlawful- practice of law, and unlawful solicitation of legal business).

Nevertheless, I believe there are other important issues about lying to one’s clients that Professor Lerman has not discussed in her article which deserve attention.

Underlying Professor Lerman’s analysis is the acceptance and recognition of law as business11 and the need to adopt, as it were, “fair business practice acts,” which is how I read her proposals.

This is important because, in this era of deregulation, law appears to be a business sorely needing regula­tion.12

On the other hand, law remains a profession as well, one that is still called “learned” by some nostalgics like myself who believe that standards of honesty and candor should be higher than what we might tolerate as a fair business practice in the open market.

In this Comment, therefore, I will suggest that in addition to Professor Lerman’s conceptualization of the ethics implicated in eco­nomic market aspects of lawyering, there may be other issues we should look at, as well, in assessing when and about what lawyers may “lie,” “mislead,” or “deceive” their clients. 13

11 There is nothing new about this observation. Several recent  articles  in  the National Law journal and American Lawyer reported on such items as partner incomes, rankings of law firms in terms of billings, size, etc. A recent outpouring of more systematic scholarship has sought to understand changes in legal practice in terms  of both demographics and economics. See, e.g., Sander & Williams, Why Are There So Many Lawyers’! Perspectives On A Turbulent Market, 14 LAw & Soc. INQ.UIRY 431 (1989) (demographic analysis); Galanter & Palay, The  Transformation  of  the  Large  Law  Firm (paper presented to American Bar Foundation Conference on Professionalism, Ethics and Economic Change, September, 1988) (on file with University of Pennsylvania Law Review).

12 Law is big business, accounting for about 1% of the total United States Gross National Product-approximately 54 billion dollars worth of business per year as of 1986 (making it larger than the steel and textile industries and comparable to auto manufacture and publishing). See Sander & Williams, supra note 11, at 434.

13 The majority of Professor Lerman’s interviews focus  on  dealings  with individual, fee-paying clients. See Lerman, supra note 1, at 703-44. Many lawyers, however, are on a salary paid by third parties, such  as  those  who are  employed  by legal aid programs, public  interest  firms,  governmental  entities,  and  pre-paid insurance plans. See C. Serron, Managing Legal Services: The Transformation of Small-Firm Practice (paper presented to American Bar Foundation Conference on Professionalism, Ethics, and Economic Change,  September,  1988)  (discussing  pre­ paid insurance plans) (on file with University of Pennsylvania Law Review). To  the extent that those lawyers deceive their  clients,  the  subject  matter  of  their  lies  and their reasons for lying may be quite different. For the  importance  of  context  in affecting lawyer decisionmaking, see C. Menkel-Meadow & B. Moulton, Who Decides? Lawyer-Client Decision-Making About Dispute Resolution, in Beyond the Adversarial Model:  Materials  and  Cases  on  Negotiation  and  Mediation  (forthcoming) (manuscript on file with the University of Pennsylvania Law Review). Professor Lerman herself points out that the dynamics  between  institutional,  rather  than  individual, clients and their lawyers may also affect the ranges of candor. see Lerman, supra note

My aim here is twofold-to express a simple moral standard for analyzing lawyer liars14 that can be debated on moral, as well as policy terms, and second, to discuss briefly a number of “lying” issues that may be overlooked when a market model of lawyering is adopted.15

II. A SIMPLE STANDARD FOR LYING: THE GOLDEN RULE OF CANDOR

Professor Lerman offers as a rule the proposition that lawyers should never deceive clients for any reason of self-interest. 16

I cer­tainly agree with this rule, but I believe it fails to cover other types of lawyer lies which are also undesirable.

Therefore, I propose  a broader rule of ·conduct: lawyers should in all respects deal with  their clients in the way they themselves would want to be treated if they were in the client’s position.

This rule goes further than do Professor Lerman’s economic regulations in dealing with both economic and non-economic deception of clients (such as strategic deception during the course of case handling), but I think it presents more complex problems of philosophical justification and practical enforcement, and therefore offer this standard for further discussion and debate.

I, at 665 n.20; see also Nelson, Ideology, Practice and Projes_sional Autonomy: Social Values and Client Relationships in the Large Law Firm, 37 STAN. L. REV. 503 (1985).

Lerman suggests that what she is most interested in is lawyers’ self­ interestedness-their interest in income and reputation. See Lerman, supra note I, at 667. Furthermore, Professor Lerman states that the twenty lawyers she interviewed about deceptive practices dealt more often with “process” concerns than “substance”-process having to do with work habits and billing practices. See id. at 670 n.41. Query whether this is really where the “deceitful” action is or whether the lawyers were more willing to own up to it as a more “acceptable” or common form of lying in the recognized competition to get business.

Lerman states that the thrust of her arguments are based on the failure of many professional responsibility writers to take account of the principal lawyer-client conflict-the lawyer’s “profit motivation.” Id. at 671.

14 It has become a common professional responsibility teacher’s pun  to adopt (or fully utilize if one already has one) a slightly southern accent to demonstrate how short an oral distance we must travel to go from “lawyer” to “liar.”

15  I  have long been interested  in  how  non-market  lawyering differs from  market or fee-paid-for-service lawyering, not only in terms of ethical strictures but in lawyer decisionmaking and resource allocation. See Menkel-Meadow & Meadow, Resource Allocation in Legal Seroices: Individual Attorney Decisions in Work Priorities, 5 LAw & PoL’Y Q 237 (1983); see also Tremblay, Toward A Community-Based Ethic for Legal Seroices Practice, (forthcoming 37 UCLA L. REV.) (1990) (forthcoming) (how different non­ market contexts, such as the provision of legal services for the poor, may  require different decision rules and “ethical” judgments in resource allocation by lawyers); Bellow & Kettleson, From Ethics to Politics: Confronting Scarcity and Fairness in Public Interest Practice, 58 B.U. L. REV. 337 (1978).

16  See Lerman, supra note I, at 684-85.

To see the advantages of this broader rule over Professor Lerman’s rule, I will first examine the rationale for her rule and then consider why her rule will not adequately protect client inter­ ests in all situations.

A. What’s Wrong with Lying? Economic Self-Interest

Professor Lerman begins her article with several definitions and degrees oflying or deceitfulness. Adopting Sissela Bok’s definition17 that lying is stated untruthfulness and deception is a broader cate­ gory of deliberate efforts to mislead which can occur by misstate­ ments, non-verbal conduct, and even by silence, Professor Lerman concludes that what is crucial is the intent to deceive.

Of course, the law currently examines intent when proscribing deception in real estate sales, commercial practices,18 and securities trading.

In some areas the law has gone further and creates liability for “negligent misrepresentation,” even without intent to deceive.19

Thus, even “unintentional” deception, may, in some circumstances, be some­ thing we will penalize.

Most of this “commercial” regulation is designed to protect against economic harm. We assume that if the purchaser knew what the seller failed to disclose or actually lied about, the purchaser would not have made the deal, or at least might have bargained for a better price.

Thus, the harm is the “unjust enrichment” of the lying or deceiving seller.

This fairly traditional conception of harm is what underlies Professor Lerman’s discussion of the harm caused by lying lawyers.

Since her interviewees lie most often out  of economic self-interest, by padding their bills, exaggerating  (in either  direction  depending on the circumstances) the amount of time and effort put into their work, and puffing about their experience and  expertise,20  we come  to see a picture of clients who are paying more than they should for legal services and perhaps also (though this cannot really be con­cluded from the data Lerman presents) getting either too little or too much service.

17 Sees. BOK, LYING: MORAL CHOICE IN PUBLIC AND PRIVATE LIFE 14 (1978).

18 See, e.g., Civ. CoDE § 1572 (West 1982) (making actual intent to deceive an essential element of an action for fraud).

19 See, e.g., CIV. CODE § 1710(2) (West 1985) (proscribing negligent misrepresentation as a category of deceit, as contrasted to intentional fraud (Cal. Civ. Code § 1572)). A new statute requires affirmative, specific disclosures in real estate transactions and provides penalties and civil causes of action for failure to affirmatively disclose regulated matters. See CAL. Civ. CODE § 1102 (West Supp. 1989).

20 See Lerman, supra note 1, at 706-20; 721-23.

Lerman concludes with a fairly simple rule: “Self-interested deception of clients by lawyers should be prohibited” 21 where self-interest appears to be equated with economic self-inter­est. Deception for such purposes is bad, she says, because lawyers will “appear greedy, immature, and unable to manage their time or face up to their mistakes.” 22

Is it only the “appearance” of greed with which we are con­cerned or is actual greed the real issue?

Why is deception for self­ interest objectionable, both in the professional context as well as in the more general human context?

Given the regulation of honest dis­closure in many commercial transactions, is there any reason to exempt the professional-client relation?

Indeed, many would argue that law in particular should not be a sharp practices, anything-the­ market-will-bear, sort of business precisely because there is some­ thing unseemly about a “helping” profession  maximizing  profits from the legal “pains” of their clients?23

In other words, while I completely agree with Professor Lerman that lawyers should not deceive out of self-interest, the rationales for such a moral  belief seem much deeper than they appear here.

To the extent that deceiv­ing another is considered “unfair” in our economic and legal system, we need to look at what unfair practices are punished and which are not.

Professor Lerman’s proposed rules requiring lawyers to be truthful in their billing practices and product (or service) advertise­ments seem entirely consistent with our general approach  to  fair trade practices in commercial transactions generally. Thus, they should hardly seem controversial.

Lawyers, in their economic capaci­ties, should be treated no differently than other producers of products or providers of services.

Our economic and moral system seems, as Professor Lerman points out, to be process-based. Let consumers have as good infor­mation as we can provide at the beginning of transactions, but we  will not insure that everyone actually makes a fair deal, the rules  seem to be saying.

21 Id. at 685.

22 Id.

23 This is, of course, exactly what lawyers (and doctors) do. Contingent fees in personal injury cases are the most obvious examples, but all fees derived from litigation can be seen this way. Is it therefore morally better or more excusable to make more money from a client’s profitable transaction (a percentage ofa successful deal)? What if the deal goes bad? It is commonplace for journalists to report the large legal fees in failed deals (such as United Airlines recent failed take-over, and the many bankruptcies that do not result in successful reorganization).

Such a morality explains why some of the propos­als for new ethics rules, which would have required the prevention of “unconscionable” transactions by lawyers,24 ultimately failed.

Thus, if lawyers honestly disclose their billing practices and fees, the sub­ stance of the deal made will be scrutinized only in the most extreme cases.25

Thus, Professor Lerman’s proposed regulations for honesty in billing and economic matters seem premised on conventional principles of commercial and consumer transactions, as evidenced by our movement in legal development from caveat emptor to caveat venditor.

The proposals here do nothing more than track the legal developments of commercial regulation.

B. When Is Lying justified: A Paternalistic Determination of Benefits and Harms to the Client

In moving from the application of consumer law principles  to the analysis of the economic relation between lawyer and client, Pro­fessor Lerman asks under what circumstances can lawyers lie to their clients.

She suggests a commonly articulated utilitarian justification for some deceptions-the benefit to the client that occurs as a conse­quence of the deception is greater than the harm. Thus, we have “altruistic deception.” 26

Lawyers seem to justify their “misstate­ments” about the progress of a legal matter by suggesting that  they are helping their clients avoid needless worry about the progress of their case.27

Here we face several difficulties.

What if some “benefit” to the client can be rationalized to protect or coincide with a self­ interested motive of the lawyer, such as in the progress report example above? Benefits and burdens do not always fall so neatly and symmetrically on opposite sides of the ledger.

More problematic, however, is the determination that must be made about what benefits the client and who makes judgments about those benefits.

24 See MODEL RULES OF PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT Rules 4.2, 4.3 (Discussion Draft,Jan. 30, 1980), which would have required lawyers to be “fair” in dealing with other participants to a negotiation and would have prevented a lawyer from participating in or assisting another in participating in an unconscionable agreement.

25 See MODEL CODE OF PROFESSIONAL. RESPONSIBILI1Y DR 2-106 (1981) (prohibiting the charging of “clearly excessive fees”); EC  2-17  (should  not  charge more than a reasonable fee); EC  2-19  (should  discuss and  agree with  client  on  basis of fees in advance); MODEL RULES OF PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT Rule 5(a) (1989) (fees must be reasonable and basis of fee must be disclosed at outset of the representation).

26 An analysis along this consequentialist line of reasoning persuades many philosophers, including Sissela Bok, that at least some lying is justified-such as lying to avoid harm to others or even to cause benefits, if no other is

27 See Lerman, supra note I, at 684.

Professor Lerman discusses two examples taken from outside of the economic emphasis of her article.

The lawyer who decides not to pass on “nasty” remarks made by a spouse during divorce proceedings may be withholding information, but does so to prevent greater harm (insult, aggravation, hurt) to the client.

Might not the motivation also be that if the client knew of the nasty remark she might want to respond and cause more (acrimonious)  work for the lawyer?

What if the client actually would decide to settle the case because she wanted no further dealings with the “nasty” spouse?

Thus, the lawyer’s judgments about sparing the client from hearing “bad” information might have ramifications for how the case is pur­sued. The substance of the case and how it is handled cannot be sep­arated from the information in question.

In giving the client the “benefit” of not hearing painful information, the lawyer also usurps the client’s ability to make judgments about how she wants her case handled.

Note here that the lawyer’s monetary interest might not be consistent with other “self-interests”- the lawyer might make more money from the additional work (depending on the fee arrange­ments) but might find the work unpleasant.28

Professor Lerman suggests that in such cases lawyers and clients can contract for the withholding of information in advance (a further inscription of the market model of lawyering).

But, can they possibly know in advance what information will need to be withheld to avoid harm to the client? If the lawyer is in doubt who should she ask? The client? A family member? Another lawyer?

In another example (one that I too encountered in practice), the lawyer learns that the client has a terminal illness (in a social security disability case) and the doctor has decided not to inform the client/ patient.29

Who decides whether to·inform the client- the lawyer, the doctor, the client’s relatives (assuming there are some-in my case there were not)? What is the harm/benefit to the client in learning about impending death?

Both of these cases involve paternalism, perhaps beneficently motivated paternalism,30 but paternalism none the less.

28 This depends on where the  lawyer  practices.  In  Los  Angeles  County,  where  I teach, practice, and live,  many  seem  to  think  divorce  lawyers  revel  in  and  indeed increase the acrimony in divorce. See Nasty, Nasty, Nasty: High Profile Divorce Wars Are Symbols of What Has Become A Tough Era/or Relationships, L.A. Times, Dec. 8, 1989, at E­ l.

29 See Lerman, supra note 1, at 684 n.92. so I use the more common phrase paternalism here for this familiar concept  but  note the gendered aspect of this  term.  The  phrase  maternalism often  connotes different emphases in such decision making. See generally C. GILLIGAN, IN A DIFFERENT VOICE (1982); S. RUDDICK, MATERNAL THINKING (1988); Menkel-Meadow, Portia In A

How is the lawyer who decides to withhold information to avoid harm to the client to be judged or second-guessed?

Are there different standards for professionals in such situations than would be applied to any per­son who has information about another human being that might be shared with that person?

As one guideline, I am reminded of one of my favorite moments in professional socialization.

Sometime in the early 1960s, on the Doctor Kildare television program, young Doctor Kildare asks old and wise Dr. Gillespe whether he should truthfully tell a patient she has a terminal disease.

Dr. Gillespe offers the following tip: If the patient asks “Am I going to live, doctor?” the patient wants  to live and should not be told of imminent death; if the patient says “I’m going to die, aren’t I doctor?,” the patient is a realist who can take it, and you can tell the truth.31

Here, the experienced professional paternalist seems to be advising Doctor Kildare, based on his many years of experience – he knows what messages patients really convey with their questions.

He can save Doctor Kildare much  time and angst by decoding their needs and wants for them.

As an incipient patient I learned my lesson well-if ever I wanted the truth from my doctor I would have to convince her I could “handle” it.

This approach did not help me with my own dying client in the social security disability case. She lived alone in a large city. I did not think she could “handle” it-but I thought she  had  the  right  to decide how to spend her last remaining months on earth.

As a lawyer I wanted her to understand the significance of the hearing she had to go to and that she might have wanted to make a will.

(Ultimately her hearing was called off – her case was so clear she received her disability benefits on the paper record. She died two months later. I felt closer to her than many of my clients because we had shared this terrible human moment of mortality).

Did I make the right decision?

Dijferent Voice: Speculations On a Women ‘.5 Law)’ering Process, 1 BERKELEY WOMEN’s LJ. 39 (1985).

31 These are not exact words,  but  my  own  recollection  of  them.  The  point  of this anecdote is  that  it  demonstrates  how  relative  and  contextual  our  judgments about truth telling might be. Given medical advances and  changes  in  therapies, including biofeedback, the patient who wants to live  might  now  be  told  the  truth  under Gillepse’s system of morality: if knowing the gravity of the illness induces the patient to take her recovery  into  her  own  hands,  the chances  of actually  recovering are much greater. See, e.g., N. CousINS, ANATOMY OF AN ILLNESS 34-48 (1979). Medical research about terminal illness indicates that over a twenty-five year period, practices about truth-telling have changed radically. Now over 70% of physicians surveyed do tell their patients while only twenty-four years ago 82% did just  the opposite. See Radovsky, “Occasional Notes: Bearing the News, 313 N. ENG.J. MED. 586 (1985).

Is Doctor Gillespe right in deciding, as a doctor with many years of experience, that he knows what is best?

The problem for me in any rule that allows us to do that which benefits or  does not harm others is that it is ultimately a decision one makes for another and our basis for judging such decisions are unclear.

C. The Golden Rule of Candor

Paternalism in ethical codes and rules, as well as in lay action, must be justified morally. Thus, it seems that paternalism must be judged in part on the basis of who makes  the  paternalistic decision.

In deciding whether or not the truth should be told, a lawyer, doctor, social worker, nurse, and yes, even a lay person, might begin with the inquiry: Would I want to be told this information if I were the client/patient?

In one sense this inquiry violates Professor  Lerman’s  rule because the professional self is the referent. In that sense, decisions about whether to tell the truth are “self-interested.”

Yet, I suspect this “self-interested” standard might lead to more truthtelling.

In part, this depends on whether it is the lawyer as per­son who asks the question or whether it is the lawyer as professional who does. There may be more than one ‘self’ implicated.

I propose such a standard because I think it will aid in resolving both the eco­nomic deception cases and cases in which lawyers engage in other forms of deception.

In addition, I think such a  standard  would  enable the lawyer to empathize with the client and take the client’s needs in the relationship more seriously32 by causing the lawyer to have to imagine what it would be like to be in the client’s shoes, for purposes of getting information.

32 This is a sort of irony in lawyer-client relations and in some sense turns the client-centered decisionmaking notion on its head. For discussions of the traditional client-centered  approach,  see  D.    BINDER   &  s. PRICE,   LEGAL   INTERVIEWING AND COUNSELING (1977); Maute, Allocation of Decisionmaking Authority Under the Model Rules of Professional Conduct, 17 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 1049 (1984); cf. Ellman, Lawyers and Clients, 34 UCLA L. REV. 717, 753-58 (1987) (acknowledging fact that even  lawyers  who seek to be client-centered must sometimes manipulate their clients, and discussing various situations in which such manipulation might be justified). I have argued elsewhere that “client-centeredness” may not be appropriate in all cases, such as when clients are quite powerful and may dominate lawyers, for economic as well as other reasons, and in cases in which the lawyer might actually know more about a particular decision and its effects than a client (such as what dispute resolution device to use in some cases). See C. Menkel-Meadow & B. Moulton, supra note 13. On the other hand, lawyer disclosure, based on a “lawyer-centered” notion  of what should be disclosed, still can lead to client-centered decisionmaking-the client will usually have more information with which to make the decision.

Let’s apply such a standard  to  the  common  problems Professor Lerman sets out.

Would a lawyer want an accountant to bill hon­estly?

Would she be willing to pay for “study hours”? (I would-I would rather have my accountant read all the recent tax regulations than rely on his “years of experience” in taking the proper. deduc­tion).

Would a lawyer want a doctor to honestly (and not with puff­ery) state his expertise and  experience?

Professor  Lerman’s proposed regulations seem appropriate, whether or not one believes that ethical matters should be regulated by specific rules or precatory exhortations, because they apply to lawyers the sort of “truth-in­ lending, truth-in-advertising, truth-in-real-estate transactions”  we now require in any number of transactions.

Thus, lawyers should clearly disclose the truth with respect to their expertise, experience, billing practices, and progress of the case. As professionals who con­sume other professional services, lawyers should be particularly sen­sitive to such matters.

Would a lawyer want to know whether or not she is terminally ill? This decision is a more difficult and subjective one to make, but still likely, in most cases, to be answered yes.

Lawyers in particular might want to be able to write wills and arrange their legal and other matters. It seems likely, however, that most people would want to know. 33

I suspect as well that most lawyers would want the  “nasty” words of an ex-spouse to be revealed to them. Even if painful, they are relevant both to legal and emotional decisions that a divorce cli­ent might be making.

To the extent that a lawyer might want to cau­tion a client not to take them too seriously in the context of acrimonious divorce proceedings, the lawyer can add additional words of advice and counsel to the reporting of the nasty  words.

Thus, to the extent that a lawyer feels a paternalistic desire to with­ hold information, it might be useful to share the reasons with the client as a way of dealing with what might be the benefits and bur­dens of disclosure and the client will be able to better understand the meaning of what has been disclosed.

Thus, I offer the proposed standard for considering  when  a  law­yer ought to be candid with a client:

Lawyers should reveal to their clients that which they would want revealed to them if they were clients.

33 This is a problem that merits more consideration than it gets here. On the other hand, it needs to be considered in light of medical ethics and medical practice which have been changing since the days of Doctors Kildare and Gillespe (and the onslaught of AIDS and related diseases) to more forthcoming medical practices, leaving fewer lawyers with these dilemmas.

What could be the objections to such a simple Golden Rule of Candor?

I honestly cannot imagine any with respect to the kinds of economic self-interest issues raised by Professor Lerman and thus, to the extent that her proposed regulations seem to legislate such standards, I support them.

Perhaps they seem so supportable to me because California has already begun to regulate with respect to fee disclosure (not exclusively in the ethical codes-in the Business and Professions Codes as well), requiring written documentation of fee arrangements, among other requirements.34

There might be objections to such regulations based on their enforceability, an argument Professor White used some time ago to justify the absence of stricter rules with respect to lying in the negotiation context.35

Here, the argument goes that if rules are not enforced, the credibility of the entire rule system may suffer as a result.

Others, notably my colleague, Professor Murray Schwartz, have argued that rules that seek to achieve high aspirational stan­dards express the best in the profession and tell us when we fall below those standards.36

Such rules would apply even to what Pro­fessor Lerman has called “altruistic” (economic) deception-the case of the lawyer that bills a paying client more and thereby subsidizes a pro bono ac tivity.37

34 See CAL. Bus. & PROF. CODE §§ 6146-49 (West Supp.  1989)  (providing various rules about fees and disclosures, and requiring that fee arrangements be in writing); CAL. RULES OF PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT Rule 4-200 (1989) (prohibiting unconscionable fee agreements).

35 See White, Machiavelli and the Bar: Ethical Limitations on Lying in Negotiation, 1980 AM. B. FOUND. REs. J. 926. Professor White’s argument was that if rules go too far afield from generally accepted practice they will be disobeyed and decrease the effectiveness and credibility of all ethical rule systems. See id. at 937. He also argued that the particular context of negotiation was so varied in different types of cases and in different regions of the country that it would be virtually impossible to create a uniformly acceptable standard of truthtelling in legal negotiations. See id. at 927. In addition, Professor White argued  that most negotiations are conducted  privately and it would be difficult in many cases to uncover and prove situations of deceit. See id. at 926. This seems a logical argument from a distinguished  commercial  law scholar who has also studied the realities of commercial practice.

As a teacher of negotiation my own views are different from Professor White and closer to those of Professor Murray Schwartz and Judge Alvin Rubin. See infra  note 36 and accompanying text (Schwartz’ views); Rubin, A Causerie on Lawyer’s Ethics in Negotiation, 35 LA. L. REV. 577, 589 (1975) (“The lawyer must act honestly and in good faith.”). In short, I think lawyers’ lies to other lawyers ought also  to  be  regulated and governed by Golden Rule standards but my exposition on that issue must await another day.

36 See Schwartz, The Death and Regeneration of Ethics, 1980 AM. B. FOUND. RES. J. 953, 963 (“Standards of performance that exceed the minimum, standards that set achievement goals, should be promulgated. They should be made known so that all lawyers can measure their conduct against them “).

37See Lerman, supra  note  l,  at 709-10.

While such Robin Hood lawyering might seem noble to some, the lawyer as client would clearly like to know she is doing a noble thing by subsidizing pro bono work. Indeed, the client who is told about such opportunities might actually encourage it, either for the moral good of it or from the instrumental tax deductibility of it.

There are more difficult issues with some non-economic decisionmaking. Would a client like to be told everything about a partic­ular procedure? Different people do have different values, desires, etc. about the need for detail or what might upset them.

Consider whether the patient wants to know all the gruesome details of an operation and whether a client really wants to know all the details about the path to having a motion decided.

Some lawyers might actually have different standards than their clients and thus applica­tion of their own values to their clients would be a particularly onerous sort of paternalism. Still, I think the expressions of paternalistic standards that suggest that the lawyer should try to figure out what is best for the client (as the lawyer determines it, even if the lawyer uses a client-centered counseling model38 ) frequently hide  the fact  that the lawyer inevitably is making judgments of her own.

Doctor Gil­lespe’s rule is expressly client-centered – it just abstracts clients  into one of two categories. (What if the smart patient simply asks the doc­tor an open-ended question: “What is my fate?”, “What illness do I have?”, “How long will I live?”, or “What’s happening to me, doc­tor?”).

Doctor Gillespe’s rule obviously vests  the  decision  whether to tell the truth in the doctor. Thus, my claim for a golden rule of  truth at least provides a standard, albeit a subjective one, for judging whether the truth should be told.

I believe that if lawyers truly con­fronted their self-interest as if they were clients, not lawyers, they would find the moral road in practice clearer (not necessarily easier to practice).

The Golden Rule approach would clearly be objected to by those like Professor Ted Schneyer, who think that moral guidelines for behavior are inadequate in the legal ethics context and specific regulations are necessary.39

38 In either its purest form, see D. BINDER & S. PRICE, supra note 32, or its more manipulative form. See Ellman, supra note 32.

39 See, e.g., Schneyer, Moral Philosophy’s Standard Misconception of Legal Ethics, 1984 Wis. L. REV. 1529, 1571 (arguing that “simply tinkering with ethics rules, or even with lawyers’ moral sensibilities” will not counter the pressures on lawyers to unduly favor their clients over third parties, and that reformers should study “the constraints and incentives that operate on lawyers in various settings and … [the] measures that might be taken to alter those constraints and incentives”).

The standard I suggest is a particularly problematic one, precisely because of its subjectivity.

As Professor Lerman points out, the implicit assumption in such objections is that without specific and enforceable regulation, lawyers will always choose the less ethical route.40

Whether a lawyer could use this double-visioned standard of considering herself a lawyer and client at the same time is difficult to assess. Aside from a sort of existential schizophrenia there may actu­ally be cases where real role conflicts would get in the way.

Would a recovering alcoholic lawyer disclose his condition to a client?

As a client he might want to know, but being able to present himself as a sober professional might be essential to his recovery and effective­ ness as an attorney.

In other cases, there may be information  only  the lawyer knows is available because she is a lawyer (like some pro­cedural matters), so it is the lawyer’s knowledge qua lawyer that would have to be applied to the decision of whether to tell the client.

III. THE OTHER LIES THAT LAWYERS TELL: LYING BEYOND THE MARKET

Professor Lerman’s focus on when and how lawyers lie to their clients is important and significant, and if her exploratory interviews could be replicated more systematically, we might learn whether lying about professional self-interest in the form of economics and reputation is in fact the most common form of deception.

40 See Lerman, supra note l, at 749-50. This argument  has  never  been persuasive to me. When I moved to California after some years of practice and teaching (including ethics) in another state (Pennsylvania) I had to sit for the Attorney’s Bar Exam, which included the MPRE (Multi-state Professional Responsibility Exam). I was advised by a well meaning practitioner friend, in cases of doubt about a question, to pick “the second most  ethical answer.”  His advice  was that the rules never required “the most ethical” conduct because there was always a lawyer’s loophole in the rules-like client consent  to  seemingly  inappropriate behavior (as in conflicts of interests) or lawyer protection of self (in exceptions to the confidentiality rule). This has proved remarkably robust advice and actually provides a useful tip for many students studying the rules for the MPRE. The only questions whose answers are quite clear involve fees and escrow  accounts  (supporting Professor Lerman’s proposals to regulate more clearly about billing  and  fee practices). The regulations, therefore, do not in my view insure “the most ethical” conduct and I think there are areas where we clearly need the kind of general moral guidelines that moral philosophers would have us consider. I cannot resist  pointing out that the California Bar Examiners have decided that the MPRE has proven somewhat too mechanical for testing ethics. Beginning this year, in addition to the MPRE, the California Bar Exam now includes ethical questions on the essay portion of the exam so that test takers must explicate their ethical choices.  If ethics is going  to be on the bar, this seems the sensible approach to me and one  that is consistent with the sort of discretionary rule I am proposing here.

Before we learn that, however, I would like to explore some of the types of deception that might occur in situations outside of the economic market for legal services to see whether the simple golden rule of truth will serve as a guide in those cases as well.

Some of the situa­tions described below may also occur in private practice and have implications for how such cases are handled, but they are not as directly related to the economic nexus between lawyer and client that is the focus of so much of Professor Lerman’s article.

In short, we might ask what distinguishes a lawyer lie from any other kind of ser­vice provider lie?

What do lawyers in particular lie about – that is dif­ferent in content from how any businessperson might “lie” about their services or products?

The easiest cases are those in which issues in public or non-market lawyering are the same as in fee-for-service lawyering: deception to clients about progress on work (delay), misrepresentation of expertise or experience, failure to disclose mistakes made in work, and the kind of strategic deception that Professor Lerman describes when a lawyer inadequately prepares a witness in order to preserve spontaneity on the witness stand. 4 1

To the extent that Professor Lerman’s proposed regulations deal with these issues, they would clearly cover the government, salaried, or public interest lawyer. 4 2

More difficult are those issues which revolve around the fact that non-market lawyering may involve different kinds of clients-estab­lishing who is being deceived may be more difficult.

The district attorney who decides to authorize questionable drug arrests because this will enhance her visibility in the community and electorate (if she sits for elective office), even when she knows that many of the arrests will not “stick,” deceives her client – “the public.”

If the D.A. could think of herself as an individual member of the public, would that change her behavior?

My guess is probably not. When the public is the client, the connection to the lawyer as public official seems atten­uated and it is hard to conceive of one individual’s view as making a difference.

41 See Lennan, supra note 1, at 736-37.

42 I have some difficulty in this context (perhaps in all  contexts)  with  a requirement that lawyers return clients’ phone calls  in  two  days.  See  Lennan, supra note 1, at 756 (proposing modification to MODEL RULES OF PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT Rule 1.4 (1983)). Who the “client” is  in  some  non-market  contexts  will  not  be as clear (such as in class actions or representation of public agencies) and  may  require more than two days for response.

In addition, much of the public, and particularly a sophis­ticated lawyer member of the civic polity, might actually expect a cer­tain amount of “deception” from political lawyers and public officials.

Moreover, in the political context, a variety of contested political justifications or interpretations of disputed law43   could serve to justify any number of such activities.

Perhaps the fear of arrest might actually decrease some of the drug trade. Who is to say that following such a course is actually deceiving the public, even if the arrests do not lead to convictions?

As fee-for-service lawyers might deceive their clients by taking on cases that have little chance of success for economic reward, analogous issues apply in the non-market context where political pressure may cause a lawyer to take a case which she knows has little chance of success but which an important member of the political team would like initiated or defended.

Here the Golden Rule of Candor may not help us because the lawyer as client might well understand why the  suit is desired and would not  want to know that it was likely to lose (there may be reasons other than winning that could motivate the lawsuit). Thus, the lawyer would be justified in withholding information about the likely outcome.

In addition to posing ethical dilemmas of candor, these situations present versions of the “role morality” problem, long applied to lawyers, 44 but also applicable to politicians and particularly to lawyer-politicians.

Can occupants of particular roles in our society-lawyers, soldiers, politi­cians-defend their actions on the basis of what the role requires of them?45

Oddly enough, like the lawyer who wants to maximize income, the public interest lawyer who wants to maximize law reform or per­sonal reputation 46 may find herself in trouble with the Golden Rule of Candor.

To the extent that the lawyer may use a different form of self-interest, usually expressed as altruistic or political interest, in bringing lawsuits to change rules or to enforce present ones, the Golden Rule of Candor would require such lawyers to fully disclose their motivations to clients who may be acting in named representa­tive capacity, such as in a class action.

43   Could a lawyer  here argue that she was attempting to test  the limits of  the  law or was advancing a claim  “for the good  faith argument  for an  extension,  modification of reversal of existing law?” See MODEL RULES OF PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT Rule 3.1 (1983); MODEL CODE OF PROFESSIONAL RESPONSIBILI1Y DR 7-102(A)(2) (1981).

44 See Wasserstrom, Roles and Morality, in THE GooD LAWYER: LAWYERS’ ROLES AND LAWYERS’ ETHICS 26-27 (D. Luban ed. 1983) (discussing how lawyers escape criticism for using morally objectionable methods in representing clients because of the demands of their role).

45 See id.; Walzer, Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands, 2 PHIL. & PuB. AFF. 160, 179 (1973) (“Moral rules are not usually enforced against the sort of actor I am considering, largely because he acts in an official capacity.”).

46 See Menkel-Meadow & Meadow, supra note 15, at 240-46 (discussing the factors that affect motivations of one group of non-market lawyers in  performing legal work).

Without repeating the volumi­nous literature on the potential of the class  action  reform  suit  to “use” and “manipulate” clients, 47 the danger here is of  the  lawyer who fails to fully disclose to the particular client all of the risks and benefits of such lawsuits.

The most obvious conflict occurs when a settlement is offered to a particular client or named plaintiff as a way of “buying” off and dismissing the lawsuit.

In my view, the Golden Rule would require no more than is already on the rule  book – the lawyer must disclose all that might happen as  best she  can.

Indeed, the use of the Golden Rule might actually facilitate candor for the lawyer would be free to say, “I think this is a very important  matter and you could personally help the situation by participating in the lawsuit (and not settling). I might do the same thing if I were in your shoes.” This forces the lawyer to be candid about his own “vicarious altruism” and to see if the client shares similar  altruistic  values.

If not, the lawyer must also recognize when individual  self-interest might lead the lawyer-as-client to want to settle.

Such candor might actually increase the “mutual political commitment” leading to “comradeship” in the lawyer-client relationship 48  that  forms  the basis of a golden rule in  the first  place-an  empathetic  understanding of the other, in this case across roles.

On the other hand, in such public interest cases, applying the Golden Rule of Candor might be more difficult because of the particular power imbalance that exists, particularly in cases where clients are low-income or otherwise vul­nerable and do not control the lawyer through economic  interests.

Here a lawyer even suggesting that “if a client” he would pursue a particular action, might be particularly hard for the client to  resist.

This is not really a problem of candor, however, but one of power relations and dominance in the professional role.

Again the  lawyer may have to be particularly vigilant to disclose more, rather than less, information to be sure the client understands as much as is possible what interests are to be served in the case and  the  actions  taken within the case.

“Public” lawyers, those in the government and those fighting government, may also take advantage of another form of “decep­tion”-using the media to “try” cases publicly and thereby  manipulate results.

This is a possibility for private market lawyers too, but access  to the media may be  greater in public interest cases.

47  See, e.g., D. LUBAN,  LAWYERS AND JUSTICE: AN ETHICAL STUDY 317-57 (1988).

48 These phrases are David Luban’s. See id. at 324-25.

Here the lawyer deceives a general “client”-the public in the case of public lawyers – but may also go beyond her own client to manipulate or deceive the jury and the larger public as well.

Such lawyers not only deceive their clients, but often bring their clients into the “decep­tion” or manipulation by encouraging them to present themselves and their stories to the media for the purpose of self-interested gain in a lawsuit.

To the extent that public49 or public interest lawyers are sup­ posed to be working for something other than the bottom line, their commitment to public service, fiduciary representation, and political and social change, their motivations may be different than those seeking monetary gain.50

Because lawyers, like all human beings, act to maximize self-interest, even if that self-interest is defined in altru­istic terms, public and public interest lawyers may deceive their cli­ents (and themselves) by attempting to maximize their  non­ monetary goals.

The ambitious prosecutor who manipulates  cases and media to gain fame and the  public interest lawyer who, instead of “cooling out” the client,51 encourages the client to pursue a claim on behalf of others, are both engaged in their own forms of lying to clients.

49 By “public” lawyers I mean those who work for the government and are thus invested with some notion of working for the public trust-an often amorphous and diffuse concept and clientele. This is to be distinguished in my view from public interest lawyers, though there is some overlap. Thus, prosecutors are clearly public lawyers, but some think they should be excluded from the public interest category when they act to enforce the status quo. The public interest lawyer is often, but not always, outside of a formal institutional structure and may or may not work for a salary. Most would include legal services lawyers and public defenders among the public interest  bar,  but these categories  are  fluid,  controversial, and ever-changing.

50 The Milton Bradley game of Careers has always captured my sense of the different motivations lawyers bring to their diverse career goals and  tasks. Early in the game players identify their own personal goals in terms of Hearts (love), Dollar Signs (money) and/or Stars (Fame), thus defining their own criteria of success. In the real world oflegal careers it seems the public interest lawyers have chosen hearts and stars over dollars (perhaps a political symbol of a gavel or hammer should  be added to provide the option of choosing social change).

51 This phrase comes from the sociologist Erving  Goffman  who  used  it  in referring to the manipulation  of  prisoners  and  other  “inmates”  of social  institutions. See E. GOFFMAN, STRATEGIC INTERACTION (1969); E. GOFFMAN, ASYLUMS (1961). The term has been applied to the practice of lawyers  persuading  clients  to  accept settlements, by manipulating or deceiving them into  thinking  their  case is worth  less than they think. See G. BELLOW & B. MouLTON, THE LAWYERING PROCESS: MATERIALS FOR CLINICAL INSTRUCTION IN ADVOCACY (1978).

Lawyers may also deceive by silence in the advice they give their clients,  not  only in  the  obvious form of not stating their own views, but by failing to express perspectives on the morality,5 2 as well as the prudence, of a particular course of action.

Here the lawyer “deceives” by saying nothing when in fact she has a particular view about what should be done. While this form of deception undoubt­edly exists in private representation as well, the cash nexus of the relationship might actually improve candor-a client who wants to “buy” the lawyer’s opinion can probably extract it for a price.

The client of the public lawyer has no equivalent leverage.

Like the private lawyers of big law firms, public lawyers are also subject to the context in which they work.

Thus, the social structure of lawyering in large bureaucratic units53 may lead to organizational practices and routinization of tasks that may deter some forms of truth-telling and may reinforce a loss of “ownership” of lawyering activity.

The rationale that “I was only following orders,” may be as true in the large government office as in the private law firm.

It is beyond the scope of this Comment to explore all of the ways non-market lawyers deceive their clients.

We need an exploratory study in this field, as Professor Lerman has done in the market con­ text,54 before we can fully canvass the  issues.  I fear the dominance  of the market economy in lawyering has begun to dominate our scholarship as well.55

This dominance may be the product of our increasing concern that law practice in its more aspirational forms is being corrupted by an increasing focus on the economic and busi­ness aspects of modern practice,56 and of our resulting desire to legislate morality in the commercial sphere.

52 See MODEL RULES OF PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT Rule l.2(b) (1983) (“A lawyer’s representation of a client … does not  constitute  an  endorsement  of  the  client’s political, economic, social or moral views or activities.”); MODEL CODE OF PROFESSIONAL RESPONSIBILI1Y EC 7-8 (1981) (“Advice ofa lawyer to his client need not be confined to purely legal considerations.”).

53 See Schwartz, The Reorganization of the Legal Profession, 58 TEX. L. REV. 1269, 1284-89 (1980).

5 4 Professor Lerman states that her sample of 20 included some government lawyers, but virtually all of the examples she gives of deception are derived from the market, fee-for service context (the exceptions being communications to  clients about the progress of work).

55 This is reflected not  only in  the focus on  ethical  issues  in  law firm  practice, but in the move in legal profession studies to focus  on  the  large  law  firm.  See  Galanter & Palay, supra note 11, at 1-110 (discussing the growth and  change at  large law firms); Sander & Williams, supra note 11, at 435-40 (same). Journalists with such publications as the National Law joumal and the American Lawyer are obsessed with covering the large private law firm. CJ Menkel-Meadow, Exploring a Research Agenda of the Feminization of the Legal Profession: Theories of Gender and Social Change, 14 LAw & Soc. INQ.UIRY 289, 306-08 (suggesting that legal scholarship on lawyers focus on other components of legal practice-such as women in the public sector).

56 Actually this fear about the commercialization of law practice is as old as the profession in the United States and the fears expressed today have their analogues in

I fear that regulation of the essentially commercial practices that Professor Lerman writes about-getting business (puffing), keeping  business  (misrepresent­ ing work progress), and making profit from business (billing prac­ tices) – does not get at the heart of what should bother us about lying or deceiving clients.

It may also represent a false security about “public-minded” lawyers, that because they do not have the financial incentives of the market, they do not deceive.

Thus, by exploring the deceptions of public, as well as private lawyers, we may get closer to what really should bother us about deception. It is not just that clients will be “bilked” out of  their money and charged unfair prices, or will choose an incompetent law­yer, though these are real evils. What should concern us about lying lawyers, what really matters in other words, is that lawyers are sup­posed to be helping and caring professionals.

If they are ultimately loyal to their clients, what does that loyalty consist of if it is based on a possibly mendacious relationship?

Would we want someone who is not truthful to us to be representing us against the world?

If  the lawyer will lie or deceive the person she is serving, what will he do with those to whom he owes no loyalty-the lawyer on the other side, the judge, the larger world out there?

If we can’t trust our lawyers, whom can we trust?

Thus, ultimately the issue of lawyers lying to clients is one of trust and power, two relatively simple, but important concepts.

If service is the ideal of the profession, should that service be consid­ered appropriately carried out if the server decides what is good for the servee?

What of the ultimate imbalance in a relationship in which the client is told to  tell everything  to the lawyer  (and it will of course be kept confidential57) but the  lawyer  may  not  be  telling everything to the client?

This suggests that another form  of  the  Golden  Rule might be:

The lawyer should be as truthful to the client as she expects the client  to  be  with her. 

This  formulation  represents  more  fully the  reci­procity imagined by the original Golden Rule.

Is true reciprocity possible in a  professional-client relationship?

many earlier periods. Compare COMMISSION ON PROFESSIONALISM, AMERICAN BAR ASSOCIATION, ” …. IN THE SPIRIT OF PUBLIC SERVICE:” A BLUEPRINT FOR THE REKINDLING OF LAWYER PROFESSIONALISM (1986) (recent concerns) with L. FRIEDMAN,

A HISTORY OF AMERICAN LAW 634 (1973) (relating that during the Nineteenth Century the “organized profession” tried to “limited  entry into the field, and  (above all) tried to resist conversion of the profession into a ‘mere’ business or trade”).

57 See MODEL RULES OF PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT Rule 6 (1983); MODEL CODE OF PROFESSIONAL RESPONSIBILITY Canon 4, DR 4-101 (1981).

Are professional relationships inherently based on non-reciprocal promises or pledges, on a necessary form of paternalism?

I think not, but until we can answer these questions, we will have to look more closely at the dif­ferent places that lawyers and clients come together. Market lawyer­ing is important, but it is not the whole story. To tell the story of economic lies (dare I call them little “green” lies) may be to avoid telling the story of more crucial lies (those that Professor Lerman’s lawyers would not tell, or the stories of the lawyers who would not even agree to be interviewed).

IV. CONCLUSION: PURSUING DECEIT OR EXTENSIONS OF THE GOLDEN RULE

Professor Lerman has attempted to make public a secret we all know – lawyers lie to their clients.

She has informed us by using an exploratory, non-systematic, empirical method to uncover what lawyers say they lie about. (Might they have deceived the researcher?)

They lie mostly about getting business, keeping business, and get­ting paid for business. There are lies about the process of legal prac­tice (the terms of the relationship between lawyer and client) and lies about the legal judgments that are made within the substantive cor­ners of a client’s matter.

Professor Lerman proposes some regula­tions to deal with these issues. I leave to others the inevitable arguments about whether these regulations will work  or  whether they need some re-drafting. In essence, I support them because they will make public and clear statements about punishable digressions from a standard of truthfulness we apply to other businesses.

What Professor Lerman’s article has revealed is that we need to explore further what really matters when lawyers lie to clients.

It is not only the economic interests at stake, but questions about the meaning of the lawyer-client relationship.

General moral rules that permit professionals (or anyone) to lie to avoid causing harm or to benefit either the client or others may be offered as a justification for some forms of deceit, but such formulations are also  paternalistic, and it is that paternalism that must be examined and justified.

Because I think Professor Lerman’s regulations are fine for the fields they treat but not sufficient for the broader issues about lying, I offer the Golden Rule of Candor for further scrutiny and objections.

It too offers a form of paternalism-lawyers deciding what they would want to know if they were in the client’s position and thus inverts, in a way, the standard notion of client-centered counseling,58 and also leaves open the possibility that such decisions will only fur­ther reflect lawyer’s self-interest.

Yet it seems to me to have the kind of common sense and appeal of the original Golden Rule-the kind that we know is moral and correct-just difficult to live up to and even more difficult to put into a professional ethics code.

Professor Lerman’s article also hints at those other crucial issues about lying and deception that must be further explored-both empirically and in the possibility of drafting both general rules and specific regulations.

Do clients lie to their lawyers? Why? (This may tell us more about clients’ views about their lawyers than anything else).

How do lies of clients to lawyers alter the responsibilities, if at all, that lawyers have to be truthful to clients (and vice versa)?

How does mutual candor affect the notions of reciprocity in the relation­ ship alluded to above?

When do lawyers lie to other lawyers (we know they do this­ some of it is justified in the rules59 ) and should they?

Would my Golden Rule apply there too?

The rule would be that  a  lawyer should be as candid with another lawyer as she would want that law­ yer to be with her. I suspect this rule would raise different expecta­tions, if we accept the notion that lawyers currently expect a certain amount of “puffing” and deceit from each other.

Could we change this by rule?60

We could explore the unthinkable – when and how do lawyers lie to tribunals and judges?

Again the rules sanction such behavior by not requiring lawyers to reveal certain facts, such as the presence of witnesses, etc., but only to reveal adverse legal authori ty.6 1

Do the rules conform to actual practices of deceit or misrepresentation by lawyers or does the incidence of lying track other dividing lines?

Should we re-open the question of trying to legislate greater candor among and between actors in the legal system?62

  • See BINDER & S. PRICE, supra note 32, at 147-50.
  • See MODEL RULES OF PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT Rule 1 (1983) (“puffing” permitted); White, supra note 35, at 927 (arguing that it is difficult to apply rules about truthfulness to a lawyer during a negotiation because a negotiator must mislead his opponent).
  • See Schwartz, The Professionalism and Accountability of Lawyers, 66 L. REV.

669, 696 (1978) (recommending a new rule that prohibits a lawyer from “assisting a client to achieve results which would be set aside in judicial proceedings”).

61 See MODEL RULES OF PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT, Rule 3.3 (1983); MODEL CODE OF PROfESSIONAL RESPONSIBILIIT DR 7-102(A)(5), DR 7-102(A)(3).

62 See MODEL RULES OF PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT Rules 4.2, 4.3 (Discussion Draft 1980); Hazard, Rectification of Client Fraud: Death and Revival of A Professional Norm, 33

Can we trust lawyers to live by a professional Golden Rule that is contrary to the rewards and incentives offered by an adversary system that prizes zealotry over truth?63

But these are questions for another day.

Professor Lerman has moved us to look into the depths of our deceitful souls  and  I, for one, think we should continue to pursue this disturbing  journey, both for the purifying philosophical and moral aspects of the inquiry and for the possibility of regulating away some of the lawyer’s deceit that has come to be so closely associated with the lawyer’s role.

EMORY LJ. 271, 272, 300 (1984) (proposing a new rule to deal with an attorney’s handling of client fraud).

63 See Frankel, The Search for Truth, An Umpireal View, 123 U. PA. L. REV. 1031, 1039 (1975) (“[T]he gladiator using the weapons in the courtroom is not primarily crusading after truth, but seeking to win.”).

The Golden Rule for Lawyers. Lying.
Click to comment

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

To Top